Monday, November 30, 2009

A Useful Understanding of History

This post will contain unfinished reflection on the following quotation:

"When in the end, the day came on which I was going away, I learned the strange learning that things can happen which we ourselves cannot possibly imagine, either beforehand, or at the time when they are taking place, or afterwards when we look back on them." – Out of Africa, 1937

It is true that storytelling reveals meaning without committing the error of defining it, that it brings about reconciliation and consent with things as they really are, and that we may even trust it to contain eventually by implication that last word which we expect from the "day of judgment." -Arendt, "Isak Dinasen"





My own work is informed by an approach to historiography taken by Hannah Arendt.  It tries to balance an appreciation for storytelling and history with a deep fear of potential uses.  This approach is shaped by life experiences of growing up in the south, research in history of rhetoric, and an attempt to teach historical judgment.

A child of the South Carolina lowcountry, I am deeply attracted to the aesthetics of tradition.  The beautiful slave plantations in still-active cotton fields called out for some sort of judgment, as well as reverence and awe.  Like other events in human history, their terrible beauty also cries out for reconsidering the past and how it is made to speak to the present.

Traditions give folks a way to understand the plausibility of events in succession and, at the same time, have the tendency to make events seem necessary and even inevitable.  This is clearly true with political traditions that create "blinders" to others' viewpoints.  It is also true in rhetorical studies, when unexamined "tradition" looks like inevitable replies in a series of theoretical exchanges between great minds.

My recent project on Cicero and his reception by Kant is an attempt to unhinge this feeling of inevitability while also accepting "tradition" as a path of influence and exchange.  If Kant had embraced more of Cicero's Stoic writings, he might have taken Cicero's emphasis on eloquence into a conception of philosophy and, in the end, human rights.  These sorts of projects, that at times verge on the counterfactual, have the ability to display the rupturing aspects of a tradition while admitting their influence.

One reason why I enjoy reading Arendt is her emphasis on the "new" and its ability to influence the present.  Using Benjamin's imagery, Arendt compares the storyteller (~historian) to a pearl diver, digging into the debris of the past to find pearls and bring them to the surface.  In the midst of our public memory stands vast areas of historical forgetting, and the storyteller has the position to make these forgotten moments known, and, in this way, to make the past relevant in the present.  Over the past few years of scholarly work, I have increasingly seen success in bringing the heretofore little known into the present in a way that reshapes the past-present link.  Archival projects and detailed textual explication are central to this process for me.

One of the other principles I take from Arendt is the avoidance of a teleological philosophy of history in my writing--destroying the concept that history is the inevitable working-itself-out toward a (progressive) end.  Especially in public address studies, my other "home," there is a tendency to write about American political movements (esp. African-American and women's movements) in a way that forgets their exceptional nature to the majority of political discourse.  Economic debates, the focus of my dissertation, show the cyclical and radically fragmentary nature of most political debate.  Making this insight convert into a convincing and readable history, vis-a-vis those social-movement-works that incorporate a stronger telos of progress, is a difficult and frustrating project.  My audiences, to at least a small extent, want to read about a triumphant tandem expansion of deliberation and equality through speech.  This democracy-enlarging impetus is embedded across rhetorical studies.

Finally, I try to teach historical judgment without teaching high-minded moralism in the classroom.  This is also a perilous task.  Arendt separates such judgment from empathy, insofar as we can never fully know the world of the past.  However, Arendt provides a resource to pull modern readers out of liberalism's abyss of suspended judgment, affirming that, through storytelling and radical histories, we can come to critique the world and the people of a time through taking up the position of a spectator, and imagining their world through shared stories and meanings to see it "through their eyes" insofar as we are capable.  A notion of rhetorical history--of seeing the world through exemplary speakers meeting a major exigence--first attracted me to this field and is not something we should cast aside.  I always try to read such persuasive dynamism back into the study of rhetorical theory as it becomes inflected by contextual social needs of an era.

To conclude, I'll come back to the opening quotation.

It is true that storytelling reveals meaning without committing the error of defining it, that it brings about reconciliation and consent with things as they really are, and that we may even trust it to contain eventually by implication that last word which we expect from the "day of judgment."

I tend to see rhetorical history not as a perfect solution to the ills of "defining," (i.e. ideas of an "essence" of something or its "true nature"), but at least a step in the right direction by highlighting artistry in contingent, unpredictable moments.  The expanded "tradition" provides many moments of exemplary practice to do this, as well as just a bizarre canon.  To study a term, "rhetoric," that was coined by its archenemy following a potential myth (Corax & Tisias) with an influential woman who was hated and loved for her role in rhetoric (Aspasia) in a field that wars with "the love of wisdom"--this has to tell you something about all knowledge as storytelling!

When Arendt says "as they really are," I read her as not being an essentialist, but instead saying that we come to reconcile ourselves with the (sometimes-radically) contingent realm of action and symbols "as it is."  In other words, we become anti-essentialists while knowing that worse views of reality preach one teleological view of history and admit the possibility of complete empathy and understanding of the past.  Instead, the "reconciliation and consent" she advocates is an acknowledgement of unpredictability and imagination that always play a role in our necessary and necessarily-incomplete judgements of the past.





3 comments:

  1. As a reader of Arendt, especially her musings on historiography, I was very excited to read this post. I will have some questions for you later Brandon, but for now, I just wanted to register my excitement.

    To everyone else, I hope to post my own reflections later this week. It is a surprising busy time of year for me as well.

    ReplyDelete
  2. Hi Brandon,

    Thanks for the amazing post! I'm taken with your post for a couple reasons--first I too am from the South Carolina Lowcountry (James Island Holla!) and then I'm also fascinated with Arendt. In particular your post helps me see this ambivalence Arendt has towards storytelling, and the unease she feels, I think, at the potential loss of a viable politics once telos and authorship assert themselves, or are asserted, through history. And yet storytelling remains a sort of fundamental to being human. Even though, I think you could argue, once you remove teleology from storytelling you're not really talking about storytelling anymore. The never-ending story is really only good because it ends. (And also that giant flying dog thing, of course.)

    The other thing your post makes me reflect on is the extent to which Kant influences what we (historians of rhetoric) do, even if only negatively, even if only in terms of a legacy of responses to Kant--he acts as the sort of plato of modernity, exiling contigency from knowledge, while we insist upon placing contigency at the center of knowing.

    My question is this--is a non-teleological history a real possibility? or does the importance of such a concept rest in our (your) efforts to realize this impossibilty? Does your (and Arendt's) resistance to teleology result in a typological or cyclical history, or in some new kind of history as yet unseen? Or is it merely the work towards these unimagined histories that matters?

    ReplyDelete
  3. Yes, I tend toward pragmatism, as the title of my post implies, so I'd reply a few ways to your very well-thought response.

    1. I would never want to leave teleological "impulses," or Teleology Lite (more taste, less filling), out of history. I conceive of this as a very local problem of the "human condition," to use an Arendtianism (?), that folks only know how to identify/act/be-in-time by learning stories and knowing the sense of fulfillment that comes with taking up a narratives--or, in other words, imagining goals and fulfilling them through narrative creation. Certainly, then, all human life is at least minimally teleological.

    2. But one important way to write history, a la Chekhov et al, is to begin to break up the epic narratives, or at least reconsider them in such a way that revolutionary action seems possible. Or, drawing from rhetorical resources, we might talk about the exercises of the progymnasmata where students are told to restructure a common fable. Other posts talk about "remapping," etc. Any way we do it, in telling history, we can write in such a way that the past is useful to the moral/ethical issues of the time.

    3. I fear that if I go too far down the questions of teleology, the ultimate teleology question arises, which is beyond my pay grade (or at least depends upon basic religious views). But one of my little historical interests is at least raising the question of how political discourse orients folks in time: politicians will always use progressive narratives, which progressive leaning rhetorical critics structured by such discourse (like myself & most of us) tend to not interrogate. On the other hand, basic questions of authority and power that gain from such discourse are (nearly) cyclical--that is, even the expectation of democracy/good government is that it reproduces itself and "final solutions" are never acceptable. Consensus is temporary; contingency is forever (sounds like a commercial for anti-engagement rings). How do we make this look "sexy" (an apt metaphor, I guess, since completion is important)? It produces a malaise in democracy. And, for me, it creates another set of arguments I have to make about why I keep looking at texts that in no way suggest happy progress and finality (my dissertation is on the constant recurring struggle for a national bank, for goodness sake)

    4. Other than this, I do not know that I am doing anything too radical (although I'm happy to hear otherwise!). New types of histories and literary forms may come that in some way restructure narratives, and new theoretical works may be written that in new ways claim death to meta-narratives. All I'm advocating is the usefulness for constantly returning to these issues, and redefining them based on the problems of the time.

    I get ethically motivated by the hope that people continue to participate in community life, and I think folks on every side of the political spectrum approach public life in the wrong way, expecting forever resolutions and "rotten" with hopes of perfection driven by religious jeremiads and the rigid ideologies that elevate the individual above the Other. So my historical-rhetorical scholarship tries to counter that impulse.

    ReplyDelete